Tuesday 24 July 2012

How do representations gain meaning?


Daniel Stern postulated six internal formats that pick up various aspects of the incoming sense data. Probably not aware of it, Stern repeats Aristotle’s problem of how the pieces from different sensory channels are parsed together. By being so distinct and clear, Stern finds exactly the right words to show the problem. I must repeat the passage from my previous post:

...the diverse events and feelings are tied together as necessary elements of a single unified happening that, at one of its higher levels, assumes a meaning. The problem with this and other such solutions is how the meaning, even a very primitive one, slips in or gets assigned or is constructed from the pieces. (Stern: The motherhood constellation, p. 89, my italics)

Indeed, by what mental function does meaning become attached to the representation, or the internal perceptual form of an object or an event? This is a typically Aristotelian problem, as Kaukua and Kukkonen pointed out in their article. An interesting Medieval attempt to solve it was presented by Ibn Sina (the Latin Avicenna), a Persian physician who lived around the turn of the first millennium (980–1037). He was an important developer of Arabian philosophical psychology and a link in the subsequent Western Medieval adoption of Aristotle’s philosophy.
Much in the same manner as Stern, Ibn Sina recognised the need to postulate a number of internal functions, or internal senses, that processed the elemental data, received by the five sense organs. I managed to retrieve a translated excerpt  in which Ibn Sina enlists the five internal senses that perform various synthetic operations on the incoming forms.

One of the animal internal faculties of perception is the faculty of fantasy, i.e., sensus communis, located in the forepart of the front ventricle of the brain. It receives all the forms which are imprinted on the five [external] senses and transmitted to it from them. Next is the faculty of representation located at the rear part of the front ventricle of the brain, which preserves what the sensus communis has received from the five senses even in the absence of the sensed object. … Next is the faculty of the 'sensitive imagination' in relation to the animal soul, and the 'rational imagination' in relation to the human soul. This faculty is located in the middle ventricle of the brain near the vermiform process, and its function is to combine certain things with others in the faculty of representation, and to separate some things from others as it chooses. Then there is the estimative faculty located in the far end of the middle ventricle of the brain, which perceives the non-sensible intentions that exist in the individual sensible objects, like the faculty that judges that the wolf is to be avoided and the child is to be loved. Next there is the retentive and recollective faculty located in the rear ventricle of the brain, which retains what the estimative faculty perceives of the non-sensible intentions existing in individual sensible objects. (Avicenna, translated in Rahman, F.(1952). Avicenna's psychology. London: Oxford University Press,  p. 31)

Ibn Sina is surprisingly modern by regarding these internal faculties as brain modules. Certainly, current brain imaging studies have shown that these modules  of the “sensible soul” do not reside in the ventricles, but the contemporary modular theories of mind follow exactly the same logic of analysis as Ibn Sina does in the excerpt. Going back to Stern’s question about constructing meaning of events I want you to pay attention to the estimative faculty that is capable of perceiving the non-sensible intentions that exist in sensible objects.

Ibn Sina understood well the impoverished character of the Aristotelian sensible forms. He asked, why does the lamb flee when perceiving a wolf. The grey, hairy form does not “inform” a particular danger. Something had to be added, and here we have a conception of meaning that “exists in the individual sensible objects” and is recognised by the estimative faculty (cf. Stern’s “protonarrative envelope”).  Thus, in addition to forms, objects seem to “emit” intentions that are perceived by an internal mental faculty. Actually, the currently popular research on the “theory-of-mind”, or "mind-reading" module represents a truly Avicennian approach to understanding how we make sense of others. I will return to this topic in due course.

According to Kaukua and Kukkonen, Ibn Sina had a sophisticated understanding of intentions.  He did not, actually, regard them as properties of objects or events that they "emit" and are then sensed by the estimative faculty. Instead, intentions vary according to the reciprocal positioning of the agent an object.  Kaukua and Kukkonen illustrate this by an example of the hunter’s way of perceiving a wolf. While the lamb flees, the hunter has a rifle and this alters the intentional balance. Now it is rather the wolf who must escape. But the hunter may be an environmentalist and does not want to harm the wolf. “Acts of meaning” (in Bruner’s terms) are not anything as such. They receive their meaning only in the concrete relationships that are established between the actor and the object.